Mathematical mysteries: Zeno's Paradoxes
by
Rachel Thomas
|
|
The paradoxes of the philosopher Zeno,
born approximately 490 BC in southern Italy, have puzzled
mathematicians, scientists and philosophers for millennia. Although
none of his work survives today, over 40 paradoxes are attributed to
him which appeared in a book he wrote as a defense of the philosophies
of his teacher Parmenides. Parmenides believed in monism, that
reality was a single, constant, unchanging thing that he called 'Being'. In defending this radical belief, Zeno fashioned 40 arguments to show that change (motion) and plurality are impossible.
The most famous of Zeno's arguments is the Achilles:
'The slower when running will never be overtaken by the quicker; for
that which is pursuing must first reach the point from which that
which is fleeing started, so that the slower must necessarily always be
some distance ahead.'
This is usually put in the context of a race between Achilles (the
legendary Greek warrior) and the Tortoise. Achilles gives the Tortoise
a head start of, say 10 m, since he runs at 10 ms-1 and the
Tortoise moves at only 1 ms-1. Then by the time Achilles
has reached the point where the Tortoise started (T0 = 10 m),
the slow but steady individual will have moved on 1 m to
T1 = 11 m. When Achilles reaches T1, the labouring
Tortoise will have moved on 0.1 m (to T2 = 11.1 m). When
Achilles reaches T2,
the Tortoise will still be ahead by 0.01 m, and so on. Each time Achilles
reaches the point where the Tortoise was, the cunning reptile will always
have moved a little way ahead.
This seems very peculiar. We know that Achilles should pass the Tortoise
after 1.11 seconds when they have both run just over 11 m, so Achilles will
win any race longer than 11.11m. But why in Zeno's argument does it seem
that Achilles will never catch the tortoise?
If you think of the distances Achilles has to travel, first 10 m to
T0, then 1 m to T1, then 0.1 m to T2
etc., we can write it as a sum of a geometric series:
10 + 1 + 0.1 + .... + 10(2-n) + ...
Now it is a little clearer. As the distance that Achilles travels to
catch the tortoise is the sum of a geometric series where the
multiplier is less than one (read more),
we know that the distance is finite (and equal to 11.11m) as the series converges.
And as he only has to travel a finite distance, Achilles will obviously
cover that distance in a finite time if he is traveling at a constant speed.
So how did Zeno manage to confuse us?
Zeno's argument is based on the assumption that you can
infinitely divide space (the race track) and time (how long it takes
to run). By dividing the race track into an infinite number of
pieces, Zeno's argument turned the race into an infinite number of
steps that seemed as if they would never end. However, each step is
decreasing, and so dividing space and therefore time into smaller and
smaller pieces implies that the passage of time is 'slowing down' and
can never reach
the moment where Achilles passes the Tortoise.
We know that time doesn't slow down in this way.
The assumption that space (and time)
is infinitely divisible is wrong (more on the physical implications
of the limiting process).
There are ways to rephrase the Achilles argument that can take our brains
in a slightly different direction. In one example, known as Thomson's Lamp,
we suspend our disbelief once again and consider a lamp with a switch that
we press to turn on, and press again to turn off.
Now, the lamp is initially off and I switch it on. After 1 minute I switch
it off. After half a minute I switch it back on. After a quarter of a minute
I switch it off. After one eighth of a minute I switch is back on and so
on, each time halving the length of time I wait before I switch the lamp
on or off as appropriate (I have very quick reflexes). After 2 minutes, (the
sum of the infinite series 1 + 1/2 + 1/4 + ...), I will have finished this
infinite sequence of actions. So at this point, is the lamp on or off?
And will it have made a difference if the lamp was initially on rather than
off?
As with Zeno's original version of Achilles, these arguments are based
on the infinite divisibility of time, and the paradox that results can be
seen to illustrating that time is not infinitely divisible in this way.
Interestingly, as mentioned above, the Achilles paradox was only one of 40
arguments Zeno is thought to have produced, and in another of his
arguments called the Arrow,
Zeno also shows that the assumption that the universe consists of
finite, indivisible elements is apparently incorrect.
So, here is where the real
paradox of Zeno lies. In his arguments, he manages to show that the
universe can neither be continuous (infinitely divisible) nor discrete
(discontinuous, that is made up of finite,indivisible parts).
This seeming contradiction in the nature of reality is echoed by
concepts from an area developed over 2000 years after Zeno lived, the
Theory of Relativity. For example, light is now thought of as
having a dual nature, behaving sometimes as a particle or photon
(discrete), and at other times like a wave (continuous). In fact even Zeno's belief in monism - in a
static, unchanging reality - which was the basis for his producing the
arguments in the first place, seems oddly similar to cosmologists
ideas about
'worldlines'
(the 'history' of a particle in spacetime) where 'the entire history of each
worldline already exists as a completed entity in the plenum of space time'
(read more).
So Zeno's paradoxes still challenge our understanding of space and
time, and these ancient arguments have surprising resonance with some
of the most modern concepts in science.
References
Zeno and the Paradox of Motion
Zeno's
race course, part 2 - Lecture
notes from the University of Washington
Zeno
at St Andrews site
About the author
Rachel Thomas is an assistant
editor of Plus.
|