BROWSE
ALPHABETICALLY
LEVEL:
Elementary
Advanced
Both
INCLUDE TOPICS:
Basic Math
Algebra
Analysis
Biography
Calculus
Comp Sci
Discrete
Economics
Foundations
Geometry
Graph Thry
History
Number Thry
Physics
Statistics
Topology
Trigonometry
|
|
Zeno’s Paradox of the Tortoise and Achilles
eno of Elea (circa 450 b.c.) is credited with creating several famous paradoxes, but by far the best known is the paradox of the Tortoise and Achilles. (Achilles was the great Greek hero of Homer's The Illiad.)
It has inspired many writers and thinkers through the ages, notably Lewis
Carroll and Douglas Hofstadter, who also wrote dialogues involving the Tortoise
and Achilles. The original goes something like this:The
Tortoise challenged Achilles to a race, claiming that he would win as long
as Achilles gave him a small head start. Achilles laughed at this, for of
course he was a mighty warrior and swift of foot, whereas the Tortoise was
heavy and slow. “How big a head start do you need?” he asked the Tortoise with a smile. “Ten meters,” the latter replied. Achilles
laughed louder than ever. “You will surely lose, my friend, in that case,”
he told the Tortoise, “but let us race, if you wish it.” “On the contrary,” said the Tortoise, “I will win, and I can prove it to you by a simple argument.” “Go
on then,” Achilles replied, with less confidence than he felt before. He
knew he was the superior athlete, but he also knew the Tortoise had the sharper
wits, and he had lost many a bewildering argument with him before this. “Suppose,”
began the Tortoise, “that you give me a 10-meter head start. Would you say
that you could cover that 10 meters between us very quickly?” “Very quickly,” Achilles affirmed. “And in that time, how far should I have gone, do you think?” “Perhaps a meter – no more,” said Achilles after a moment's thought. “Very well,” replied the Tortoise, “so now there is a meter between us. And you would catch up that distance very quickly?” “Very quickly indeed!” “And yet, in that time I shall have gone a little way farther, so that now you must catch that distance up, yes?” “Ye-es,” said Achilles slowly. “And
while you are doing so, I shall have gone a little way farther, so that you
must then catch up the new distance,” the Tortoise continued smoothly. Achilles said nothing. “And
so you see, in each moment you must be catching up the distance between us,
and yet I – at the same time – will be adding a new distance, however small,
for you to catch up again.” “Indeed, it must be so,” said Achilles wearily. “And so you can never catch up,” the Tortoise concluded sympathetically. “You are right, as always,” said Achilles sadly – and conceded the race. Zeno's
Paradox may be rephrased as follows. Suppose I wish to cross the room. First,
of course, I must cover half the distance. Then, I must cover half the remaining
distance. Then, I must cover half the remaining distance. Then I must cover
half the remaining distance . . . and so on forever. The consequence is that
I can never get to the other side of the room. What this actually does is to make all motion impossible, for before I can cover half the distance I must cover half
of half the distance, and before I can do that I must cover half of half
of half of the distance, and so on, so that in reality I can never move any
distance at all, because doing so involves moving an infinite number of small
intermediate distances first. Now, since motion obviously is
possible, the question arises, what is wrong with Zeno? What is the "flaw
in the logic?" If you are giving the matter your full attention, it should
begin to make you squirm a bit, for on its face the logic
of the situation seems unassailable. You shouldn't be able to cross the room,
and the Tortoise should win the race! Yet we know better. Hmm. Rather
than tackle Zeno head-on, let us pause to notice something remarkable. Suppose
we take Zeno's Paradox at face value for the moment, and agree with him that
before I can walk a mile I must first walk a half-mile. And before I can
walk the remaining half-mile I must first cover half of it, that is, a quarter-mile,
and then an eighth-mile, and then a sixteenth-mile, and then a thirty-secondth-mile,
and so on. Well, suppose I could cover all these infinite number of small distances, how far should I have walked? One mile! In other words,
At
first this may seem impossible: adding up an infinite number of positive
distances should give an infinite distance for the sum. But it doesn't –
in this case it gives a finite sum; indeed, all these distances add up to
1! A little reflection will reveal that this isn't so strange after all:
if I can divide up a finite distance into an infinite number of small distances,
then adding all those distances together should just give me back the finite
distance I started with. (An infinite sum such as the one above is known
in mathematics as an infinite series, and when such a sum adds up to a finite number we say that the series is summable.) Now
the resolution to Zeno's Paradox is easy. Obviously, it will take me some
fixed time to cross half the distance to the other side of the room, say
2 seconds. How long will it take to cross half the remaining distance? Half
as long – only 1 second. Covering half of the remaining distance (an eighth
of the total) will take only half a second. And so one. And once I have covered
all the infinitely many sub-distances and added up all the time it took to
traverse them? Only 4 seconds, and here I am, on the other side of the room
after all. And poor old Achilles would have won his race.
ADDENDUM
o
that you don't get to feeling too complacent about infinities in the small,
here's a similar paradox for you to take away with you.
THOMPSON'S
LAMP : Consider a lamp, with a switch. Hit the switch once, it turns it on.
Hit it again, it turns it off. Let us imagine there is a being with supernatural
powers who likes to play with this lamp as follows. First, he turns it on.
At the end of one minute, he turns it off. At the end of half a minute, he
turns it on again. At the end of a quarter of a minute, he turns it off.
In one eighth of a minute, he turns it on again. And so on, hitting the switch
each time after waiting exactly one-half the time he waited before hitting
it the last time. Applying the above discussion, it is easy to see that all
these infinitely many time intervals add up to exactly two minutes.
QUESTION: At the end of two minutes, is the lamp on, or off?
ANOTHER QUESTION: Here the lamp started out being off. Would it have made any difference if it had started out being on?
|
|
|