Last Time | Next Time |
Kellie suggested that Frank Baum's story The Queen of Quok would make good infinity reading, too!
I'll flash through them, you vote, and some of you will get an extra "get out of quiz free" card.
Don't wait for the last minute! (It usually shows, if you do....:_ )
The power set of a set \(S\) is the set of all of S's subsets, and denoted \(P(S)\).
Turns out the even natural numbers are as numerous as the natural numbers themselves, which seems troublesome. Subsets created from a set by throwing out a bunch of elements are not supposed to be the same size as the original set -- but things are a little different when it comes to infinite sets.
I want revisit one of the things we looked at last time: Assigning students on the infinite number of infinitely large buses (but doing it from a graph):
(for this one, you can see that the two sets are actually in a one-to-one correspondence; for the others, we see that the natural numbers are at least as big as an infinite number of copies of the natural numbers -- but that should seem pretty obvious...!:).
If I put the people in the Hotel in the first column (we'll call it Bus 1), you can see that they go into the rooms numbered by the triangular numbers: 1, 3, 6, 10, 15, ....
\[ n \longrightarrow \frac{n(n+1)}{2} \] More generally, for the person sitting in seat \(s\) on bus \(b\), \((b,s)\), \[ (b,s) \longrightarrow \frac{1}{2}\left(b^2+b(2s-3)+s^2-s+2\right) \] This is a one-to-one correspondence between the natural numbers and infinitely many copies of the natural numbers.
Looking at it another way, we can see that the rational numbers (ratios of natural numbers, and the negatives of those) are the same size (have the same cardinality) as the natural numbers:If we think of a bus/seat pair as a fraction, \((b,s) \equiv \frac{b}{s}\) we see that every positive rational number has its own room within the natural numbers. In fact, they have infinitely many rooms, since, for example, \[ \frac{1}{1} = \frac{2}{2} = \frac{3}{3} = \frac{4}{4} = \ldots \] all get rooms (but they're the same rational number!).
Question of the day:
We're going to revisit the natural numbers first, to show that their power set is bigger than the naturals. (How will we know that?)
We often denote a set by using braces, e.g. \(S=\{1,2,3\}\) is the set of the first three natural numbers.
We say that \(a\) is an element of \(S\) if \(a\) is contained in \(S\), and we write \(a \in S\). So \(1 \in S\), \(2 \in S\), and \(3 \in S\). We deny that an object is in \(S\) this way: \(4 \notin S\).
And if the sets are finite, the proper subset is always smaller, but if the set is infinite, we may actually be able to throw away elements of a set and not change the size of the set!
1 3 3 1 |
(We know that since each row of Pascal's triangle adds to a power of 2.)
This property holds true for all finite sets -- and it turns out to be true for infinite sets, too!
Here's a silly video to illustrate how the power set grows with sets of increasing size. (Thanks to Dr. Towanna Roller (Asbury University) and her daughter Kristyn Roller (UK) for this one!)
Imagine not: then we can set up a one-to-one correspondence between the natural numbers and its power set,
\(n \in N\) | \(ss(n) \in P(N)\) |
1 | \(N\) |
2 | {} |
3 | odds |
4 | primes |
5 | {1,2} |
6 | evens |
7 | Fibonaccis |
... | ... |
We can find a subset of \(N\) that's not on the right hand side! That is, we can show that it's not really one-to-one, because there's a subset that's not at the dance (a tango!) -- that had no partner, and so is sitting quietly and sadly at home, perhaps even crying quietly....
We construct this sad set as follows:
We will call \(ss(n)\) the partner subset corresponding to a natural number \(n\); and we construct the set \(A\), the lonely set, by the following rule: for each natural number \(n\), we either add \(n\) to \(A\) or not, depending on whether \(n \in ss(n)\):
If \(n \in ss(n)\), then \(n \notin A\)
If \(n \notin ss(n)\), then \(n \in A\)
And by this means, we can see that \(A\) is different from every \(ss(n)\) that's gone to the dance, and so \(A\) says to itself sadly, "Well, I guess tonight I'll be dancing by myself!"
That symbol that you've been familiar with for all your lives, $\infty$: you thought it stood for a single thing; but it stands for a whole collection of monstrously big things, all too big to really think about properly. (Well, Cantor did!:)
"I love you more than the power set of your set of infinite love."
Amen!